Interpretive frameworks
Epistemological probability
Symmetry
Classical theorists hold that probability derives from the symmetry of a situation (dice, coins, poker).
“Principle of Equal Probability”
The theory of chances consists in reducing all events of the same kind to a certain number of equally possible cases, that is to say, to cases whose existence we are equally uncertain of, and in determining the number of cases favourable to the event whose probability is sought. The ratio of this number to that of all possible cases is the measure of this probability, which is thus only a fraction whose numerator is the number of favourable cases, and whose denominator is the number of all possible cases.
Laplace 1814 – Philosophical Essay of Probabilities
- Primary example: games of chance (dice, cards, coins…)
- Challenge: whence “equal probabilities” for possible outcomes?
Logical / evidential
Logicists hold that probability relates the syntactic structure of theory language.
Evidentialists hold that probability relates known evidence to a proposed hypothesis.
Given a scientific hypothesis
, we can intelligibly ask: how probable is on present evidence? We are asking how much the evidence tells for or against the hypothesis. We are not asking what objective physical chance or frequency of truth has. A proposed law of nature may be quite improbable on present evidence even though its objective chance of truth is 1. That is quite consistent with the obvious point that the evidence bearing on may include evidence about objective chances or frequencies. Equally, in asking how probable is on present evidence, we are not asking about anyone’s actual degree of belief in . Present evidence may tell strongly against , even though everyone is irrationally certain of . Williamson 2000 – Knowledge and Its Limits
- Primary example: weather events, scientific facts
- Challenge: What is meant by “evidence tells for a hypothesis”?
- Challenge: Cf. Subjective probability
Subjective probability
Beliefs
Bayesians hold that probability measures the degrees of belief of persons.
Your degree of belief in
By degree of probability, we really mean, or ought to mean, degree of belief.
De Morgan 1847 – Formal Logic, or, The Calculus of Inference, Necessary and Probable
Probability “is a measurement of belief qua basis of action” (F. Ramsey).
Dutch Book Theorem If your beliefs violate the Kolmogorov Axioms of Probability, then someone can devise a bet you would take and necessarily lose money.
- Primary example: scientific hypotheses and facts
- Challenge: ‘Coherence’ (axioms of probability) leaves much open
- Challenge: doesn’t allow being ‘wrong’ about probability (only rationality)
- Challenge: hard to ascertain beliefs or preferences
Physical probability
Frequencies
Frequentists hold that probability derives from patterns in repeated trials.
Probability of
probability is nothing but that proportion [of births of males and females]
Venn 1876 – The Logic of Chance
- Primary example: statistical tests and studies
- Challenge: One-shot events like decay of a single uranium atom
- Challenge: Reference class problem
Propensities
Propensity theorists hold that probability measures a causal power or tendency inhering in objects.
I am, then, to define the meaning of the statement that the probability, that if a die be thrown from a dice box it will turn up a number divisible by three, is one-third. The statement means that the die has a certain ‘would-be’; and to say that the die has a ‘would-be’ is to say that it has a property, quite analogous to any habit that a man might have.
C.S. Peirce 1910 – Notes on the Doctrine of Chances
- Primary example: actions/habits of living organisms; decay of single uranium atom
- Challenge: “Suppose a sick patient has propensity to trigger a medical test. Do positive medical tests have propensity to have come from a sick patient?”
- Challenge: Other problems shared with Frequentists.
Scenario | Natural framework |
---|---|
Rolling a die | Classical |
Do gravitational waves exist? | Evidentialist or Bayesian |
Decay of single uranium atom | Propensity |
Polling voters | Frequency |
Winning at slot machine | Classical |
Significance test | Frequency |
MAP criterion | Bayesian |
Tornado occurence | Evidentialist, Bayesian |
Chance that Jane goes to movie | Propensity |
Relativity Theory is true | Bayesian, Evidentialist |
Chloroquine cures COVID | Frequency |
Lab Leak Hypothesis | Bayesian, Evidentialist |
Case studies
COVID testing
- Background rate: 1% of population has COVID
- Sensitivity: 95% chance positive test on people with COVID
- Selectivity: 90% chance negative test on people without COVID
Bayesian approach
Priors:
Question
Find
Solution
Bayesian calculation:
We may view this formula (rewrite) as “update priors in light of evidence”:
Division into case for denominator:
Frequentist approach
Type I error rate: 10% Type II error rate: 5% Significance level: 10%
Election polling
Say 1,000 people are polled for the 1836 US election. 52% for Harrison 48% for Van Buren
Frequentist approach
Write
Confidence interval for sample mean
Confidence interval relation:
Thus:
Typical imposed “significance level” is 5%. Thus, the poll is significant if the 95% window excludes 50% for Harrison. Therefore, this poll is not significant.
Bayesian approach
We need to know